Morality is absolute. Moral choices are not, or they would not be choices. Rand was very clear on why a rational, volitional being needs morality. Anyone is free to question that thesis; I am not going to repeat it. khalling asked: "explain the difference btwn objective and absolute."
Alone on his island, Robinson Crusoe could choose to fish, or plant, or hunt. But he had to choose. The fact of choice is a moral absolute. The content of the choice is not: it is contextual. In society, pursuing a specific career is a moral choice. Many options are available. The fact that you must choose something - even choosing to be a moocher - is a moral absolute. What you choose is not absolute, but contextual; and context determines what is objectively moral, regardless of the ethical implications.
Rand called her theory of egoism "Objectivist ethics." In her essays, she wrote mostly about morality and very little about ethics. She took the English language as she found it. Despite the fact that she knew perhaps four languages (Russian, French, German, and English), Rand did not delve into linguistic analysis. In other languages, "ethics" and "morality" do not exist as separate words. In English, we commonly use the words interchangeably, just as we do for "weight" and "mass" or "speed" and "velocity." When we have technical discussions, the distinctions become important.
I was working in transportation when a colleague suggested that I take a class in computer programming "so the people in data processing can't hand you a bunch of baloney." I took a class and liked it. I went to work as a programmer. On a project, no one wanted to write the user manual. Having published a few articles and two small books, I did the documentation. I became a technical writer. When the current recession started, I took a part-time job as a security guard. As the economy continued to slide, I needed a four-year degree to even apply for work as a technical writer, so I earned one in criminology. Those were all moral choices, but ethics had nothing to do with it.
khalling wrote: "Ethics are external and morality is internal." As a quick summary, or talking point, that does indicate the difference between morality and ethics. But as above, you can make many "external" moral choices. Where I work, a husband and wife also work. I went three weeks without a network connection and four without a telephone. On his second day, she called around and got him what he needed. She did not do that for me. It was certainly moral of her to take care of her husband. But I regard it as unethical. Nepotism is contrary to the culture of a democratic, capitalist workplace.
Completing a masters in social science, I took a graduate class in "Ethics in Physics." I found that technical societies for geologists, geographers, engineers of all kinds, have different statements of professional ethics. They all boil down to "be nice; do no harm." But they are all different in detail, and properly so. The work of a geographer is materially different than that of a geologist.
I also attended a seminar in the teaching of ethics to graduate students in counseling. As I recall, their statement of ethics runs 25 pages. Moreover, the point of the seminar was that to practice as a counselor - to practice _ethically_ - you need to do more than attempt to apply the ethics document. Life is more complicated than that: the document is a guide. Ethical choices are highly contextual.
khalling wrote: "Ethics and Morality are blood brothers just like geometry and algebra can be expressed in similar ways." In fact, of course, blood brothers are genetically unrelated. Becoming blood brothers is more like a marriage ceremony. If you look at any modern textbook in geometry for mathematics majors, you will find no drawings. It is all algebra. I understand the point: proper ethical conduct in society depends on a correct morality of self-interest. khalling just wrote those one-liners offhand or off the top her head. I have been at this for almost 90 minutes because her question merited a considered reply. As for the analogy to geometry and algebra, having re-read ITOE, I just started George Boole's "Law of Thought" and I had a similar observation: reading Boole after Rand was like finding the algebra in geometry.
MM likes to point out my answers are always quick without deeper analysis. I agree. Not really appropriate on this site to give 25 pages of statement regarding Ethics-perhaps a link. I am ok with Rand combining Ethics and Morality-both meet the standard of 'code of values.'
Right on the money. Reality is existence. Morality is how we choose to respond to it. And often, not to choose is ultimately making a choice. Robinson Crusoe is a fine example.
explain the difference btwn objective and absolute. Ethics are external and morality is internal. how is that conflating? the distinction is non conflicting. mind body dichotomy is BS
Is morality absolute? What a thought. "Morality (from the Latin moralitas "manner, character, proper behavior") is the differentiation of intentions, decisions, and actions between those that are "good" (or right) and those that are "bad" (or wrong). The philosophy of morality is ethics. A moral code is a system of morality (according to a particular philosophy, religion, culture, etc.) and a moral is any one practice or teaching within a moral code." (Wikipedia)
For myself, I remove the words good and bad since they come too close to altruistic rationalizing justifications. I use right and wrong as derived from Objectivist Philosophy.
The simple answer is NO, it's contextual to an individual and circumstantial basis, but properly derived from an objectivist point of view, 1. meaning to understand the definitions of the words and names and actions applied 2. that actual observations of those things involved are made 3. that the reasoning ability of the individual is applied with rational logic to the abstracts and concepts generated eliminating contradictions 4. that a certain truth is identified 5. actions are taken based on that truth then that morality is consistent within that philosophy for that individual for that set.
Within Objectivist Philosophy there is one unitary principle: “This is John Galt Speaking” in Atlas Shrugged: "Whatever may be open to disagreement, there is one act of evil that may not, the act that no man may commit against others and no man may sanction or forgive. So long as men desire to live together, no man my(sic) initiate—do you hear me? No man may start—the use of physical force against others." But there is also another, that being that the individual decide and act for his/her self interest.
My first Zen Master gave me a similar unitary principle, appropriately Westernized: "It's OK to be a human being and make all the mistakes a human makes, as long as you never intentionally harm another, more particularly yourself."
But I've found myself, against my choice and intention, to be placed in situations where it was my job and necessity to initiate fatal force against others. That was at an age before my Objectivist Philosophy had cured and set to such a point that I could resist or refuse the force that placed me in that situation in the first place. And I've had a 40 +/- year battle within my self ever since, which is what led me to my Zen Master in the first place. The battle lines have swung back and forth and probably will until I die.
There's going to be a lot of disagreement with the above, but I believe that we can reach consensus if we first start with the definitions, the philosophy, and the contexts.
Yes I agree. Breaking someone's Window is wrong, but if you're dangling off of a sky scraper, you'll probably be forgiven. Still wrong though and the owner could totally Sue you. Sound fair?
For a horrible murder, can not capital punishment be regarded as delayed (self) defense carried out by our agent, the government ? After all, if the murderer had failed in his intent and the potential victim killed him, that would be self-defense (at least back when the law made sense).
Is stealing always wrong? What if you're stealing from a thief? Or, perhaps, a better example: lying? Is it always wrong? If you're baing robbed and the thief asks you to give up all that you have and you give up part of it and lie that there's no more, is that lying immoral? You can extrapolate that to our relationship with the government.
A thief does not act by the rules of civilized society and thus does not deserve to be treated as if he did. I did our taxes yesterday. Sickening ! - and I feel guilty for not just writing "Go to Hell" and sending that in. Ah, for the FEAR of retribution ! (If a hundred million people did it, then what - and is it at all possible to organize such a thing ?) Just dreaming.
I think that in a black and white example, lying and stealing are not only moral, but I would recommend them. The problem is in the gray areas, when a person starts to rationalize morality based on what is profitable for himself. Unfortunately, the gray areas could be 90% of the spectrum.
So, if I plunge a knife into your chest, are you saying that is moral? Trying to make sense of your statements. I think the knife sticking out of your chest would be harshly real.
Perhaps this can be more appropriately approached as being on the side of reality = being moral. Being on the side of non-reality is immoral. A different approach would be immorality precedes evil behavior. Morality precedes good behavior. As an Objectivist you must know that your own life has value but others are to be respected.
Does your life have value to me? Sometimes, sometimes not.
You seem to present a circular argument, that immorality precedes evil behavior. But does evil behavior necessarily follow immorality? Can good behavior follow immorality?
I'm not sure what "being on the side of reality" means. As I started with, plunging a knife into your chest would certainly be a very "real" act. How does that equate to being moral?
And what exactly is non-reality? Dreams? Delusions? Drug induced altered consciousness? Please expand as I'm at a loss to understand this concept.
Plunging a knife in my chest (unless in self-defense) is probably a result of imagining that I am a threat to you and that you need to change my reality (kill me), to preserve your life. Hence the thought that preceded your action was immoral and led to evil. Only actions are truly evil.... the thought was only the seed planted, not the fruit. Morality being an absolute has its roots in reason. If you are reasoning correctly (i.e. always striving for reality in your reasoning and life) you will be a moral person.
Perhaps you are too young or maybe live a sort of cloistered existence (good for you!) but if you live long enough you will run into evil people. They generally are gossips. To them (and most people in general) reality is simply what you can convince another person that it is (think Washington, D.C.). That doesn't change reality, but it does set in motion evil behavior from those who want to change reality. Since reality has nothing to do with what you think or feel about it you must change your thoughts or the thoughts and feelings of others in order to have enough "rule by consensus" to overtake another person's boundaries, hence "changing" reality and morality. That is the essence of evil.
To be a truly moral person you need to understand that your personal goals should be basically two-fold: 1) Loss prevention and 2) Personal growth. Evil people will follow this pattern: 1) Loss creation and 2) Depleting others.
The portrayal of Elsworth Toohey as the ultimate evil person was one of Ayn Rand's greatest achievements. He lived an evil and immoral life constantly attempting to change reality and ultimately met his match. I would refer you to his patterns.
Ayn's portrayal of the ultimate hero/moral person of Howard Roark was unparallelled. He lived a life of struggle and growth NEVER wavering in his commitment to reality and reason and in the end, won.
Delusions, dreams, altered consciousness, etc. are inner states. Reality concerns the things of this earth and of existence in the physical realm. They have a place in non-reality but not the creation of non-reality. Perhaps you can think of delusions, etc. as "watching a movie" about life ... but is only a two-dimensional replica of it.
As a final good will gesture to you, I sincerely hope that you never run into an evil person, but if you do, please remember that you can fight them off with just a bit of reality and reason. Keep your intellectual armor ready at all times.
The knife was merely a thought experiment using the parameters that you specified. I wish you no ill will.
So, let's take your two postulates - loss prevention and personal growth. Whose loss? And what form of personal growth?
Let's take the example of Mother Theresa. I could make a very good argument that she meets your two postulates. Yet, there are Objectivists who would paint her as the ultimate evil - one who lived a life of altruism.
I don't know if you consider yourself an Objectivist (or at least don't remember). So, can you reconcile your postulates with Mother Theresa? How would you characterize her?
No. Pretending that I thought that plunging the knife into my chest was something that I wanted ...and then convincing others that it was the "right" thing to do is immoral...particularly if by doing this you have successfully stolen from me with the approval and support of others.
This is what you are doing. You are ignoring the conceptual framework of Objectivist Ethics. Then you bring up a specific situation of which we do not have all the facts. You can't do this in engineering. How is different than saying 2+2 does not equal 4. Because what if you have 2 apples and 2 oranges, that's not 4 oranges. The conceptual framework needs to be part of the discussion and you can't subvert it by context dropping. It has been well defined in Objectivism. IF you have a specific question, state it. Let's take capital punishment. Objectivists would say 1.You have a right to self defense. 2.When those right's are violated, the one violating another's rights, forfeits their own. 3. Under the law there is proportionality and you do not have to have capital punishment 4.Capital punishment is not immoral. next?
Your question is not fundamental to O. Ethics. But you start with the idea that you own yourself. You can kill yourself. The dilemma is can you ask someone else to help you kill yourself? They are a free agent, if they want to help they can. From a legal/practical perspective, there are challenges. But the fundamental position is clear. Doctors do it all the time. What is your objection with step two?
It is moral to die when none of your values can be attained. John Galt was willing to die rather than to lose Dagny. I am willing to die right now rather than to vegetate to death in a coma while on machines.
You bring up an interesting question and posit a creative definition. However, there is an obvious situation which tests your hypothesis: capital punishment.
There is also the part of morality that originates from religion. For those who believe in life after death or that death is a doorway to the next life, death isn't a finality or termination to existence, which greatly affects moral choices of all kinds. The other effect it has is to change the whole discussion about dying and morality. I think that in order to discuss your question, you have to be able to define the lens from which you are eying death.
The original question posed by iroseland was "when is it moral to die". I bring up capital punishment as an obvious test of this question. I have observed that one's position on this item is largely determined by one's belief in the afterlife. Those who believe in an afterlife are much less likely to oppose the practice, while those who disbelieve are much more likely to oppose it.
In addition to the quandary of capital punishment, one must also evaluate the following moral quandaries: defensive killing, abortion, suicide, assisted suicide, and sacrifice to save another. To me, all of these situations must be addressed in order to comprehensively answer the question: "when is it moral to die?"
Real case from the coast: A man and his beloved dog walked along the beach. A sneaker wave came and took the dog. The man ran into the sea to save it. The dog made it; the man did not. He saved what he loved; that was his goal. That he died was very unfortunate and he probably didn't even have the time to ponder the morality of the situation. I would have acted just like him.
Absolutely. The moral quandary of self-sacrifice must be addressed by any moral code in order to be thorough and consistent.
This man obviously held his dog in higher regard than himself. If one is a dog-lover, that may seem reasonable and laudable. To those who are not dog-lovers, however, that act seems foolish. Therefore, the real question is this: does there exist an absolute morality that covers situations like this? This is the answer to the original question.
Please, blarman, don't sound like an objectivist beginner. The man doubtfully held his dog in higher regard' than himself. When we love somebody or something, we do all we can for them. He underestimated the currents; accidents happen. By the way, those people I have met who are pet lovers, tend to be nicer than others, more gracious and hospitable - like their souls are warmer.
The original question was about how to evaluate the morality of death and its agents. I was only outlining the considerations to be taken into account and the opposing viewpoints on the matter. My comments were neither a reflection on dog-lovers or non-dog lovers except to note that their motivations will likely cause their actions to be evaluated very differently by others.
To be an Objectivist (not my claim BTW) is to be able to study out an argument and reasonably describe it rather than jump to conclusions based on emotional attachment to ideology.
If you keep the moral code simple, such as it is morally right to pursue your values, then it can be an absolute morality.
I've heard objectivists say that Rand bridged the is-ought gap because a human can have no value without life, therefore the highest value has to be the individuals life, with anything that benefits that life being morally valuable. Humans ought to value their lives above all else because without their livesnothing has value.
This is still taking into account the man who would die to save his dog or his country. He values his life primarily, but his life would lose most if not all of its value without freedom or his dog. He doesn't sacrifice himself, he trades his life for the things that are most valuable to the type of life he wants.
"If you keep the moral code simple, such as it is morally right to pursue your values, then it can be an absolute morality."
Absolute implies that it is not subject to the whims of any one person - that it is exterior to the subject. Morality may either be absolute (principles that apply to anyone and everyone) or it may be personal. This is one of the age-old fundamental questions of philosophy: the belief in the presence (or absence) of an absolute or universal moral code.
I perceive the situation thus: A) the posited existence of an absolute morality independent of any individual, B) the individual's perception/understanding of such a morality and C) the choice whether or not to adhere to it - all steps on a ladder. Alternately thus: existence, comprehension of existence, knowledge of scope and detail, and then choice to obey or disregard.
If one rejects the notion of universal morality, one immediately has decided that only moral relativism applies. The problem in this is that one is explicitly acknowledging factors that totally undermine society. Humanity depends on community/society for existence, so based on the evidence of society itself, I reject the idea of the absence of universal morality.
If one acknowledges the concept of universal morality, then comes the challenge of attempting to define it. Here is where the realm of a "personal" morality (as most people think of it) comes into play, but in reality it is not a change to the morality, but rather one's subjective interpretation of such. We do not actually have the power to define that morality (the laws of choice and consequence are outside our realm of control at the time being) and it exists independent of any given individual. All we can do is attempt to ascertain to the best of our knowledge, experience and learning what is entailed in this absolute morality. That is why there are hundreds of theologies and moral philosophies present in humanity - there is a lack of agreement on (and especially adherence to) what would comprise that single absolute morality (assuming of course that it exists).
In the case of the man and his dog, the man - under his personal interpretation of morality - determined that the risk of saving the dog (even at the cost of his own life) was a worthy transaction. That was a personal choice. Does it violate any kind of universal morality? I don't have any idea, and unless the man somehow reports to us on the consequences of his decision, I don't know that we can know with any certainty!
He did not necessarily hold his dog in higher regard than himself, but he certainly held it in higher regard than what he perceived as the danger to himself. There is a difference. Had he been told that he would surely die and his dog would surely live, would he still have made the same choice? We cannot know, but can only pose the question. The answer may be yes, in which case your original proposition is proven true, or it may be no, in which case it is not proven. The problem is, we can never know because knowledge is not absolute nor ubiquitous.
Interesting take. I would have thought just the opposite. Those who believe in an afterlife would want the individual to continue living in the hopes that they would repent and thus find salvation. While those that do not believe in an afterlife (particularly Objectivists) would think that it is just necessary to get to the termination as quickly as possible. Why string out something, since all are going to die in any case, and society has merely determined that this specific individual should forfeit their existence earlier than it ordinarily would.
As for the others, yes, I agree. There is a post for abortion - I thought that one was enough for the time being, but have alluded to a couple of the others on various posts.
In the conversations I have had on the subject of capital punishment, atheists and liberals have been overwhelmingly against the practice, while Christians and conservatives are for it. Why?
For Christians, one can look at things a couple of different ways. In a capital offense, the person has already been convicted of murder - the intentional taking of another's life. Many just want to send that person on to God for judgement with the perhaps uncharitable view that that individual has lost their chance to repent.
I don't believe in anything quite so cynical. I believe that we are protecting society and setting forth the penalty for murder and that this is the primary reason: to deter others from considering such a course of action.
The other point to contemplate is that those who are given the death sentence are not really any different from those given a prison sentence of a life term. In neither case is rehabilitation judged to be a probability. For all the cry and hue about "cruel and unusual punishment", why not languishing away in prison?
For atheists and liberals, I always get a lot of dancing around the subject and non-answers, so I can only speculate that the real reason they disagree is that they fear the unknown and they transfer this fear onto themselves as a proxy for the convict. That fear prevents them from condemning someone to cease to exist.
The thing that would be ironic if it weren't so tragic is that these same people in general support the principle of abortion, which is no less the termination of life than capital punishment and upon a person who is far less worthy of the punishment. I can find no rationale for this contradiction unless it is not a rationale, but rather fear which in fact is making the decision.
I've noticed the same correlation between religion and the death penalty, and for the most part I like your explanation of it.
I also like the way you think of the death penalty, as a deterrent. Obviously it isn't going to stop all murders, I doubt anything really will, but it keeps rational people from committing murder. Or I should say borderline rational, as a mostly rational person very seldom contemplates going through with murder.
I don't think the death penalty really deters too many people though. I don't have a problem with death, I rarely talk about capital punishment cause it isn't very interesting to me. But I do like cost efficency, and while I'm not sure how much it costs to hand out a death sentence, I would say in most cases it would be more productive to reach an agreement with the murderer. I know it sounds ludicrous, but unless the person is full on insane I think you could find a use for him.
I'm not sure, maybe I'll think about it more and try to solidify my line of thought.
I hesitate to label the deterrent effect as my primary advocacy for the consistency of capital punishment with natural law, but I will acknowledge that deterrent is part of the reason for law in the first place. If there is no punishment for a certain action, why should one fear such a choice in the first place? We can label it incentive vs disincentive if we want, but really, it is all about trying to persuade every member of society to live by the same rules. The only reason punishments exist (except as part of the natural order) is to explicitly define specific actions that run contrary to the goals of society. If we go back to value and how it applies to influencing decision-making, deterrent only becomes effective when the punishment for a given crime exceeds the benefits for committing such. The problem with murder in this regard (as in the case of rape) is how does one economically price such an act - and further how many people could pay back such a cost so incurred? Thus one of the fundamental quandaries related to the sentencing for murder.
As for cost efficiency, you'll go south in a hurry if you go there because the current legal system is an endless maze of appeals and definitions of what constitutes "cruel and unusual punishment". Because of this legal morass, it is far more economical to pay $30,000+ a year (see http://www.vera.org/sites/default/files/...) for the life of the convict than the multiple millions it takes to exhaust the appeals process and eventually carry out the sentence. To me, this isn't as much a remark on the efficacy of capital punishment as it is on the non-efficacy of the criminal justice system itself, as well as a general commentary on society as a whole. :S
Agreed. It is interesting to look back on the legal precedents and systemic changes that have taken place in the past 300 years. One can spend entire careers looking at the prominent decisions in legal history and debating them. Which might be fun - in their own individual threads. ;)
There is little deterrence in the death penalty. It is merely a means to eradicate someone who has demonstrated that they have no claim on the resources required to live.
Let me venture an opinion -- if the people you're referring to are liberals and just happen to be atheists, then the lack of logic is understandable. Liberals, being in essence adolescents with no desire to grow up, are illogical. Beings atheists, for them, does not come from any logical analysis. I think that if you were to talk to atheists who are not afflicted with permanent adolescence, you will find that capital punishment is a logical and a needed response to capital crimes.
I agree. What I found, however, is that I haven't found any examples of such outside the Gulch (though please understand that I am not discounting the possibility that some exist). I think that says a lot for the members of the Gulch - they actually think about their positions rather than just regurgitate what they get from friends/family/media/etc.
I certainly cannot speak for all of faith, but for Christians, particularly Catholics, the death penalty is deemed to be a sin. It is also believed that it is still possible for a person up until their dying breath to seek redemption via repentance.
I too can only speculate about the atheists. But again, I don't see why they would have any qualms about capital punishment.
"I certainly cannot speak for all of faith, but for Christians, particularly Catholics, the death penalty is deemed to be a sin."
Really? That's a new one to me. A sin for the convict or the executioner? And what is the biblical justification for such a claim? That a curious stand.
Genesis 9: “Whoever sheds man’s blood, by man his blood shall be shed, for in the image of God He made man."
Romans 13: "...rulers are not a cause of fear for good behavior, but for evil. Do you want to have no fear of authority? Do what is good and you will have praise from the same; for it is a minister of God to you for good. But if you do what is evil, be afraid; for it does not bear the sword for nothing; for it is a minister of God, an avenger who brings wrath on the one who practices evil."
That right there is the Christian justification FOR capital punishment.
Old Testament, my friend. That all changes in the Gospels - which is the prime basis for the Catholic church (if not all Christianity).
The Bible is often mentioned in debates about the death penalty. Supporters quote the Exodus passage, eye for eye, while opponents appeal to Ezekiel (33:11): "As I live, says the Lord God, I swear I take no pleasure in the death of the wicked man, but rather in the wicked man's conversion, that he may live." In fact, such use of the Bible (finding a "proof text" to affirm one's point of view) is inappropriate.
Scripture scholars teach us to understand the Bible (and its individual books) in historical context: when it was written and why. Thus considered, there is an ambivalence about capital punishment in the Scriptures.
Clearly, the Hebrew Scriptures allowed the death penalty (for a much longer list of offenses than our society would be comfortable with—for example, striking or cursing a parent, adultery, idolatry). Yet, as we see in Ezekiel and many other passages, there is also an attempt to limit violence and to stress mercy. In the Christian Scriptures, Jesus' life and teachings (see the Sermon on the Mount, Matthew 5:1-7:29) focus on mercy, reconciliation and redemption. (It may also be instructive to recall that Jesus' death was itself an application of the death penalty.) The basic thrust of the Gospels supports opposition to the death penalty.
Indeed, the early Church (for example, in the writings of Clement of Rome [died 101 A.D.] and Justin Martyr [d. 165]) generally found taking human life to be incompatible with the gospel. Christians were not to participate in capital punishment. Later, after Christianity became the religion of the Roman Empire, opposition to the death penalty declined. Augustine recognized the death penalty as a means of deterring the wicked and protecting the innocent. In the Middle Ages, Thomas Aquinas reaffirmed this position. The new Catechism of the Catholic Church reflects this tradition, stating that the death penalty is possible in cases of extreme gravity. However, the Catechism adds: "If bloodless means [that is, other than killing] are sufficient to defend human lives against an aggressor and to protect public order and the safety of persons, public authority should limit itself to such means, because they better correspond to the concrete conditions of the common good and are more in conformity to the dignity of the human person" (#2267). Clearly, then, the bishops' opposition to the death penalty is in accord with universal Church teaching.
Romans is New Testament. The quote from Genesis predates even the OT Law of Moses, as it was given in the time of Noah. The Bible is clear and consistent on the capital punishment issue before the OT Law, during the OT Law, and after the OT Law. The Apostle Paul even is seen saying in Acts 25 "I am standing before Caesar’s tribunal, where I ought to be tried. I have done no wrong to the Jews, as you also very well know. If, then, I am a wrongdoer and have committed anything worthy of death, I do not refuse to die; but if none of those things is true of which these men accuse me, no one can hand me over to them. I appeal to Caesar." So, you can infer from his statement that though he did not believe he did anything worthy of death, he agreed in principle that there were actions that DID merit this punishment.
It is true my reply didn't address most of what you wrote. I wasn't trying to give you the brush off - sorry if you took it that way. Since this isn't a religious forum, when the subject comes up I do my best to just address what I believe to be misconceptions or misstatements about what Christianity is and leave it at that. Your point was "death penalty = sin" in Christian morality. I only wanted to reply to that point, and I hoped to demonstrate this isn't the case. What you brought out in your longer explanation didn't really reinforce your position, IMO. You showed there has back and forth attitude changes by prominent people. If it is sin, why the wavering? Also, I don't understand how you can hold that the Catholic Church teaches the death penalty is sin and then bring out a quote from the Catholic Catechism that says it is permissible in certain cases. I could have gone there in my original reply, but I think the two of us may have been the only ones interested in that discussion and it would have come off like two people having a religious argument, which I don't intend to do. I just wanted to show it wasn't really reasonable to say that Christianity opposes capital punishment based on what we see in the Bible. No disrespect intended to you with the lack of addressing what men may have thought later on. I'm just keeping my focus on the text of the book.
Respectfully, I disagree. The majority of your argument relies solely on the authority of the Catholic Church to interpret doctrine. If one rejects such authority, the statements of officials of the Catholic Church become - respectfully - the statements of ordinary men rather than statements from the ordained ministers of God.
I applaud you for standing up for your beliefs - please don't misinterpret me. I just don't happen to agree with either the logical assertions being made nor do I accept the authority of the Catholic Church (and apparently neither does Lionel). What we have agreed on is the authority of the Bible, but not the interpretation thereof. Thus an impasse.
So the Catholic Church considers capital punishment equivalent to murder? I would be interested in the Biblical justification for such a policy in order to understand the rationale, as it doesn't seem to make sense.
The Catholic bishops of the United States have provided careful guidance about this difficult issue, applying the teaching of the universal Church to our American culture. Along with the leadership assemblies of many Churches (for example. American Baptists, Disciples of Christ, Episcopalians, Lutherans, Presbyterians), the U.S. bishops have expressed their opposition to the death penalty. First articulated in 1974, the bishops' position is explained in a 1980 statement, Capital Punishment. Individual bishops and state conferences of bishops have repeated in numerous teachings their opposition to the death penalty.
In their 1980 statement, the bishops begin by noting that punishment, "since it involves the deliberate infliction of evil on another," must be justifiable. They acknowledge that the Christian tradition has for a long time recognized a government's right to protect its citizens by using the death penalty in some serious situations. The bishops ask, however, if capital punishment is still justifiable in the present circumstances in the United States.
In this context, the bishops enter the debate about deterrence and retribution. They acknowledge that capital punishment certainly prevents the criminal from committing more crimes, yet question whether it prevents others from doing so. Similarly, concerning retribution, the bishops support the arguments against death as an appropriate form of punishment. The bishops add that reform is a third reason given to justify punishment, but it clearly does not apply in the case of capital punishment. And so they affirm: "We believe that in the conditions of contemporary American society, the legitimate purposes of punishment do not justify the imposition of the death penalty."
As with the debate in our wider society, it is important to move behind the discussion of deterrence and retribution to get to the heart of the bishops' position. The statement does just that, by discussing four related values that would be promoted by the abolition of the death penalty.
First, "abolition sends a message that we can break the cycle of violence, that we need not take life for life, that we can envisage more humane and more hopeful and effective responses to the growth of violent crime." The bishops recognize that crime is rooted in the complex reality of contemporary society, including those "social conditions of poverty and injustice which often provide the breeding grounds for serious crime." More attention should go to correcting the root causes of crime than to enlarging death row.
Second, "abolition of capital punishment is also a manifestation of our belief in the unique worth and dignity of each person from the moment of conception, a creature made in the image and likeness of God." This belief, rooted in Scripture and consistently expressed in the social teach- ings of the Church, applies to all people, including those who have taken life.
Third, "abolition of the death penalty is further testimony to our conviction, a conviction which we share with the Judaic and Islamic traditions, that God is indeed the Lord of life." And so human life in all its stages is sacred, and human beings are called to care for life, that is, to exercise good stewardship and not absolute control. The bishops recognize that abortion, euthanasia and the death penalty are not the same issue, but they each point to the same fundamental value: safeguarding the sanctity of life.
Fourth, "we believe that abolition of the death penalty is most consonant with the example of Jesus." In many ways this final point summarizes the other three: the God revealed in the life of Jesus is a God of forgiveness and redemption, of love and compassion—in a word, a God of life. The heart of the bishops' position on the death penalty, then, is found in the gospel.
Gut-level reactions may cry out for vengeance, but Jesus' example in the Gospels invites all to develop a new and different attitude toward violence. The bishops encourage us to embody Jesus' message in practical and civic decisions.
Let's see, a convicted prisoner is alive one minute, and another minute is dead. Not from natural, accidental, nor self-inflicted (although they consider suicide murder as well) causes, so pretty much murder.
Only if one totally disregards the concept of justice and responsibility for one's own actions. The murderer chose his course and is being rewarded with the fruits of his labors. The executioner is merely carrying out the justice dictated by the law and granting the offender his request. To equate those two functions to me is a grave disservice to the concept of justice and law itself.
You are welcome and have the right to hold to that philosophy. I can not reconcile the advocated position with either logic or theology and thereby politely decline.
So I am only assuming because I don't know your position that you are both atheist and pro-capital punishment. Please correct me if I am mistaken.
You might be surprised, but I don't find these positions to be contradictory at all. You are also the rare one I have spoken to that holds both positions. Probably because people in the Gulch tend to be more pragmatic and logical rather than solely ideological. Kudos to you.
As I pointed out, the moral contradictions occur when one can not point out the need or moral justification for allowing someone deemed by society to be forever an enemy to such to continue to live off society. I can respect any position as well as it is reasonable - it is the irreconcilable contradictions that rub me wrong.
Well, I started this by saying that I was mostly talking about Catholics. That's my upbringing and what I know reasonably well. Haven't studied differences to Lutherans, Protestants, Baptists, Mormons, etc.
That said, I also don't take everything espoused by the Catholic church hierarchy as "gospel." As you say, they are men, and men are fallible (and no, I don't believe in the infallibility of the Pope).
The "purist" O's will say that I cannot do that, that I must accept all teaching of those in the hierarchy of my faith otherwise I don't really hold with my faith. That's bogus, as I can come to my own conclusions as well as the church hierarchy.
"What is morality, or ethics? It is a code of values to guide man’s choices and actions—the choices and actions that determine the purpose and the course of his life. Ethics, as a science, deals with discovering and defining such a code.
The first question that has to be answered, as a precondition of any attempt to define, to judge or to accept any specific system of ethics, is: Why does man need a code of values?
Let me stress this. The first question is not: What particular code of values should man accept? The first question is: Does man need values at all—and why?" AR, The Virtue of Selfishness The code of values derives from Man qua Man
"The first question is: Does man need values at all—and why?"
One can not act without values. Self-determination presupposes the ability to evaluate one's current position in comparison to a future position. If one has no values, one has no basis for comparison and therefore can not act. The need for values is therefore presupposed and inherent when one defines man as being self-aware. There is no great moral mystery here. The question is really about which morality (value system) to adopt.
For example, computer code is just exactly that: a value system. Without it, the computer sits lifeless and useless. With it, it now has instructions on which it can perform computations and work.
No, the first question is this: "Presupposing that man has the capability to act, the key lies in defining HOW he should act, i.e. which set of rules should govern his decisions."
So, actually, you answered the question in the affirmative. Yes, man needs values, because we have reason. We don't merely act by instinct or training. We can choose, thus, as you describe, then we need rules by which those choices are made.
Now, since we have put that away, how about the genesis of this whole thread - are those codes absolute? A computer program is absolute. That code can provide for different choice given inputs (the "if, then, else" situation), but you cannot violate the fundamentals of what the code means - "if" checks one thing against something else. You can either find that it agrees or doesn't agree, but you cannot come to the conclusion "blue."
I'll quibble slightly with you here. My point was to observe that one can not question the importance of values and retain self-determination. Thus it becomes an irrelevant question.
Ironic that you posted the example of computer code, as I agree with you and used exactly the same analogy elsewhere on this very thread!
Please justify that morality only derives from religion. I think that there are several here who would disagree. Why cannot morality exist in and of itself?
I think the problem lies in that many people assign the term "religion" to an organized practice of such with followers, leaders, etc. such as Christianity, Islam, Buddhism, Taoism, etc. Where this falls short is in recognizing that religion is nothing more than a defined set of shared values and also includes the cults of Global Warming, animal rights, nature worship, political ideologies such as Progressivism, Marxism, etc. Even atheism is a religion.
From Merriam-Webster: : the belief in a god or in a group of gods : an organized system of beliefs, ceremonies, and rules used to worship a god or a group of gods : an interest, a belief, or an activity that is very important to a person or group
If you only use the 3rd definition, I can see how you might come to that position. That is not the common definition.
Given that, do you believe that what one holds as important is the only thing that defines the moral code? Are there not things outside of the specific individual's sphere of importance that have an impact on morality?
I believe that there is a universal morality that exists whether or not we choose to follow it. The reason I believe this is partially due to my faith, but also due to the inexorable laws of nature. If one could really define morality arbitrarily, would not one be selecting the choice/repercussion pairings? If we have the ability to define morality, would we not get to select choice AND consequence? Since that remains beyond our capability as humankind (though there are definitely some ideologies who want to pretend otherwise), I conclude that morality exists independent of our justifications or desires to the contrary!
Until we can define and control the consequences for actions, it is pure illusion to believe that humans have any ability to control what I will call natural morality. We can pass laws to whatever effect we want. It really doesn't matter how well intentioned (or not) we are, we have no power to rebut these natural laws and their consequences.
I will use the example of sexual promiscuity. One of the results of unfettered sexual activity is the probability that one will contract one of the many sexually transmitted diseases. Despite society's permissiveness regarding sexual norms, traditional values most accurately reflected this reality: if you have sex with multiple partners, you take a high medical risk. On the other hand, if you remain chaste and monogamous, your probability of contracting one of these diseases drops to zero!
The natural laws of economics are the same way. No matter how much governmental officials want to believe in Keynesian economic theory, it runs contrary to natural economics and therefore always fails as a consequence. Taking money from the private sector so government can spend it has never and can not provide efficient or lasting private sector growth. High tax policies result in a retarded private sector economy. Those are laws of nature that can not be re-written - no matter how hard progressives want to believe otherwise.
Philosophy is individual because we all have self-will and self-determination. We determine our own morality or code of ethics (to me, they are identical). The bigger question is HOW we determine our own moral code: do we trailblaze and attempt to derive our own moral code or do we adopt a moral code laid down by someone else? Whichever way we go, we must also take a look at the motivations which drive us in our decision, as those motivations are the core of our morality.
"Do no harm." This simple statement implies that I can differentiate one person from another and that I have self-awareness: I can differentiate myself and my limits from my environment and I can recognize the presence and boundaries of other self-aware entities. On top of that, I accept that just as I value my own self-awareness and self-determination, others may come to the same conclusion. My own actions and boundaries are delimited when they have an effect on others.
The problem with the statement "do no harm" is that it is also highly nebulous and subject to several nullifying conditions. "Harm" indicates damage or an adverse effect, which I may or may not be able to properly perceive with respect to the other person. Unless that other person shares my same level of knowledge and morality, what I may interpret as "harm" may not equate to theirs. Further, what if in order to remove an injured victim from a burning building I must move them and risk exacerbating the existing injury? I will do harm either way. Therefore I find this statement to be too dependent on subjective rationalization to be useful as a moral code.
The second realization is that we are not individual creatures: we can not survive on our own. Humankind requires society for economics, procreation, etc. So in our personal search for a moral code, we must also search for a moral code that best fits not only for ourselves, but also fits others. Thus is derived the push for evangelicalism - the attempt to harmonize the moral codes of society on a single base. Out of this grows society itself.
Since we have derived that man must individually choose morality, but that society must agree on a joint morality in order to function, it is reasonable for our cooperative moral code to than apply to everyone the same way - or to be absolute. Those who violate society's moral codes are then cast out or confined. So I would argue that morality is absolute first in the social context of the social contract.
Second, we must also evaluate that if each individual is seeking their own betterment, but that we are bound together as a society, then the aggregate result is that society - as a function of individual self-determination - is also seeking for betterment. In this way, we are also seeking for a unifying set of principles that enables all the full rights of self-expression while lifting society as a whole. This sought-for societal morality will also be absolute - even if it is conceptual.
So yes, morality is absolute - from either an individual or a societal standpoint - but we individually have the self-determination to either adopt and practice that absolute morality or not.
"Reality is an absolute, existence is an absolute, a speck of dust is an absolute and so is a human life. Whether you live or die is an absolute. Whether you have a piece of bread or not, is an absolute. Whether you eat your bread or see it vanish into a looter’s stomach, is an absolute."-Galt Morality meets the test of an absolute. The Law of Identity
No, you seem to be buying into (or offering) a package deal. First morality is not ethics. Rand was not alone in conflating them. The statements you quoted above are, indeed truths. Morality as formally defined is absolute. Ethics, however, is not absolute, but objective. If Ayn Rand had intended it, she would have called her philosophy "Absolutism." She called it "Objectivism." Objectivism considers context. Some things are absolute; not everything is.
Then please tell me, 'cause I'm just interested in the exchange of ideas. Today has been very satisfying. Morality, economics, science - quite a good day.
"Very well, as individuals we all die. This brings us to the second half of the question: Does homo sapiens AS A BREED have to die? The answer is: No, it is NOT unavoidable.
We have two situations, mutually exclusive: Mankind surviving, and mankind extinct. With respect to morality, the second situation is a null class. An extinct breed has NO behavior, moral or otherwise.
Since survival is the sine qua non, I now define “moral behavior” as “behavior that tends toward survival.” I won’t argue with philosophers or theologians who choose to use the word “moral” to mean something else, but I do not think anyone can define “behavior that tends toward extinction” as being “moral” without stretching the word “moral” all out of shape.
We are now ready to observe the hierarchy of moral behavior from its lowest level to its highest."
Read the whole speech. It's worth reading... I personally really like the part about the baboons. And at the end of the speech maybe you'll meet Jeff Allen... and me.
The next paragraph might be encouraging to some Objectivists here, so I thought I'd share it in hopes of getting people to read the whole speech:
"The simplest form of moral behavior occurs when a man or other animal fights for his own survival. Do not belittle such behavior as being merely selfish. Of course it is selfish. . .but selfishness is the bedrock on which all moral behavior starts and it can be immoral only when it conflicts with a higher moral imperative. An animal so poor in spirit that he won’t even fight on his own behalf is already an evolutionary dead end; the best he can do for his breed is to crawl off and die, and not pass on his defective genes."
Alone on his island, Robinson Crusoe could choose to fish, or plant, or hunt. But he had to choose. The fact of choice is a moral absolute. The content of the choice is not: it is contextual. In society, pursuing a specific career is a moral choice. Many options are available. The fact that you must choose something - even choosing to be a moocher - is a moral absolute. What you choose is not absolute, but contextual; and context determines what is objectively moral, regardless of the ethical implications.
Rand called her theory of egoism "Objectivist ethics." In her essays, she wrote mostly about morality and very little about ethics. She took the English language as she found it. Despite the fact that she knew perhaps four languages (Russian, French, German, and English), Rand did not delve into linguistic analysis. In other languages, "ethics" and "morality" do not exist as separate words. In English, we commonly use the words interchangeably, just as we do for "weight" and "mass" or "speed" and "velocity." When we have technical discussions, the distinctions become important.
I was working in transportation when a colleague suggested that I take a class in computer programming "so the people in data processing can't hand you a bunch of baloney." I took a class and liked it. I went to work as a programmer. On a project, no one wanted to write the user manual. Having published a few articles and two small books, I did the documentation. I became a technical writer. When the current recession started, I took a part-time job as a security guard. As the economy continued to slide, I needed a four-year degree to even apply for work as a technical writer, so I earned one in criminology. Those were all moral choices, but ethics had nothing to do with it.
khalling wrote: "Ethics are external and morality is internal." As a quick summary, or talking point, that does indicate the difference between morality and ethics. But as above, you can make many "external" moral choices. Where I work, a husband and wife also work. I went three weeks without a network connection and four without a telephone. On his second day, she called around and got him what he needed. She did not do that for me. It was certainly moral of her to take care of her husband. But I regard it as unethical. Nepotism is contrary to the culture of a democratic, capitalist workplace.
Completing a masters in social science, I took a graduate class in "Ethics in Physics." I found that technical societies for geologists, geographers, engineers of all kinds, have different statements of professional ethics. They all boil down to "be nice; do no harm." But they are all different in detail, and properly so. The work of a geographer is materially different than that of a geologist.
I also attended a seminar in the teaching of ethics to graduate students in counseling. As I recall, their statement of ethics runs 25 pages. Moreover, the point of the seminar was that to practice as a counselor - to practice _ethically_ - you need to do more than attempt to apply the ethics document. Life is more complicated than that: the document is a guide. Ethical choices are highly contextual.
khalling wrote: "Ethics and Morality are blood brothers just like geometry and algebra can be expressed in similar ways." In fact, of course, blood brothers are genetically unrelated. Becoming blood brothers is more like a marriage ceremony. If you look at any modern textbook in geometry for mathematics majors, you will find no drawings. It is all algebra. I understand the point: proper ethical conduct in society depends on a correct morality of self-interest. khalling just wrote those one-liners offhand or off the top her head. I have been at this for almost 90 minutes because her question merited a considered reply. As for the analogy to geometry and algebra, having re-read ITOE, I just started George Boole's "Law of Thought" and I had a similar observation: reading Boole after Rand was like finding the algebra in geometry.
Ethics are external and morality is internal. how is that conflating? the distinction is non conflicting. mind body dichotomy is BS
For myself, I remove the words good and bad since they come too close to altruistic rationalizing justifications. I use right and wrong as derived from Objectivist Philosophy.
The simple answer is NO, it's contextual to an individual and circumstantial basis, but properly derived from an objectivist point of view,
1. meaning to understand the definitions of the words and names and actions applied
2. that actual observations of those things involved are made
3. that the reasoning ability of the individual is applied with rational logic to the abstracts and concepts generated eliminating contradictions
4. that a certain truth is identified
5. actions are taken based on that truth
then that morality is consistent within that philosophy for that individual for that set.
Within Objectivist Philosophy there is one unitary principle: “This is John Galt Speaking” in Atlas Shrugged:
"Whatever may be open to disagreement, there is one act of evil that may not, the act that no man may commit against others and no man may sanction or forgive. So long as men desire to live together, no man my(sic) initiate—do you hear me? No man may start—the use of physical force against others." But there is also another, that being that the individual decide and act for his/her self interest.
My first Zen Master gave me a similar unitary principle, appropriately Westernized: "It's OK to be a human being and make all the mistakes a human makes, as long as you never intentionally harm another, more particularly yourself."
But I've found myself, against my choice and intention, to be placed in situations where it was my job and necessity to initiate fatal force against others. That was at an age before my Objectivist Philosophy had cured and set to such a point that I could resist or refuse the force that placed me in that situation in the first place. And I've had a 40 +/- year battle within my self ever since, which is what led me to my Zen Master in the first place. The battle lines have swung back and forth and probably will until I die.
There's going to be a lot of disagreement with the above, but I believe that we can reach consensus if we first start with the definitions, the philosophy, and the contexts.
Or do you mean that morality is an absolute in the sense that there is only one true morality and people who differ from it are wrong?
So, murder can be morally wrong, but capital punishment can be ethically right - ?
be regarded as delayed (self) defense carried out
by our agent, the government ? After all, if the
murderer had failed in his intent and the potential
victim killed him, that would be self-defense (at
least back when the law made sense).
as if he did.
I did our taxes yesterday. Sickening ! - and I feel
guilty for not just writing "Go to Hell" and sending
that in. Ah, for the FEAR of retribution ! (If a hundred million people did it, then what - and is
it at all possible to organize such a thing ?)
Just dreaming.
relevant point starts at 14.34
justice.
Immorality is the systematic re-creation of reality in an attempt to gain that which you haven't earned.
Ethics are principles of self-interest based upon reality and reason.
A different approach would be immorality precedes evil behavior. Morality precedes good behavior.
As an Objectivist you must know that your own life has value but others are to be respected.
My life has value. I agree.
Your life has value to you. I agree.
Does your life have value to me? Sometimes, sometimes not.
You seem to present a circular argument, that immorality precedes evil behavior. But does evil behavior necessarily follow immorality? Can good behavior follow immorality?
I'm not sure what "being on the side of reality" means. As I started with, plunging a knife into your chest would certainly be a very "real" act. How does that equate to being moral?
And what exactly is non-reality? Dreams? Delusions? Drug induced altered consciousness? Please expand as I'm at a loss to understand this concept.
Morality being an absolute has its roots in reason. If you are reasoning correctly (i.e. always striving for reality in your reasoning and life) you will be a moral person.
Perhaps you are too young or maybe live a sort of cloistered existence (good for you!) but if you live long enough you will run into evil people. They generally are gossips. To them (and most people in general) reality is simply what you can convince another person that it is (think Washington, D.C.). That doesn't change reality, but it does set in motion evil behavior from those who want to change reality. Since reality has nothing to do with what you think or feel about it you must change your thoughts or the thoughts and feelings of others in order to have enough "rule by consensus" to overtake another person's boundaries, hence "changing" reality and morality. That is the essence of evil.
To be a truly moral person you need to understand that your personal goals should be basically two-fold: 1) Loss prevention and 2) Personal growth. Evil people will follow this pattern: 1) Loss creation and 2) Depleting others.
The portrayal of Elsworth Toohey as the ultimate evil person was one of Ayn Rand's greatest achievements. He lived an evil and immoral life constantly attempting to change reality and ultimately met his match. I would refer you to his patterns.
Ayn's portrayal of the ultimate hero/moral person of Howard Roark was unparallelled. He lived a life of struggle and growth NEVER wavering in his commitment to reality and reason and in the end, won.
Delusions, dreams, altered consciousness, etc. are inner states. Reality concerns the things of this earth and of existence in the physical realm. They have a place in non-reality but not the creation of non-reality. Perhaps you can think of delusions, etc. as "watching a movie" about life ... but is only a two-dimensional replica of it.
As a final good will gesture to you, I sincerely hope that you never run into an evil person, but if you do, please remember that you can fight them off with just a bit of reality and reason. Keep your intellectual armor ready at all times.
So, let's take your two postulates - loss prevention and personal growth. Whose loss? And what form of personal growth?
Let's take the example of Mother Theresa. I could make a very good argument that she meets your two postulates. Yet, there are Objectivists who would paint her as the ultimate evil - one who lived a life of altruism.
I don't know if you consider yourself an Objectivist (or at least don't remember). So, can you reconcile your postulates with Mother Theresa? How would you characterize her?
http://www.nouvelles.umontreal.ca/udem-n...
How is different than saying 2+2 does not equal 4. Because what if you have 2 apples and 2 oranges, that's not 4 oranges.
The conceptual framework needs to be part of the discussion and you can't subvert it by context dropping.
It has been well defined in Objectivism. IF you have a specific question, state it. Let's take capital punishment. Objectivists would say
1.You have a right to self defense.
2.When those right's are violated, the one violating another's rights, forfeits their own.
3. Under the law there is proportionality and you do not have to have capital punishment
4.Capital punishment is not immoral.
next?
I like your analysis. However, doesn't that depend upon ensuring that step 2 is absolutely correct?
Also, what about the situation of a "mercy killing?" Were the person's right to self-defense violated if they asked for the action?
And of course, I could bring up the aspect of self identity, but that is the subject of another post, so won't drag it up here.
But you start with the idea that you own yourself. You can kill yourself. The dilemma is can you ask someone else to help you kill yourself? They are a free agent, if they want to help they can. From a legal/practical perspective, there are challenges. But the fundamental position is clear. Doctors do it all the time.
What is your objection with step two?
There is also the part of morality that originates from religion. For those who believe in life after death or that death is a doorway to the next life, death isn't a finality or termination to existence, which greatly affects moral choices of all kinds. The other effect it has is to change the whole discussion about dying and morality. I think that in order to discuss your question, you have to be able to define the lens from which you are eying death.
In addition to the quandary of capital punishment, one must also evaluate the following moral quandaries: defensive killing, abortion, suicide, assisted suicide, and sacrifice to save another. To me, all of these situations must be addressed in order to comprehensively answer the question: "when is it moral to die?"
wave came and took the dog. The man ran into the sea to save it. The dog made it; the man did
not.
He saved what he loved; that was his goal. That
he died was very unfortunate and he probably didn't even have the time to ponder the morality of the situation. I would have acted just like him.
This man obviously held his dog in higher regard than himself. If one is a dog-lover, that may seem reasonable and laudable. To those who are not dog-lovers, however, that act seems foolish. Therefore, the real question is this: does there exist an absolute morality that covers situations like this? This is the answer to the original question.
beginner. The man doubtfully held his dog in
higher regard' than himself. When we love somebody or something, we do all we can for them. He underestimated the currents; accidents
happen. By the way, those people I have met
who are pet lovers, tend to be nicer than others,
more gracious and hospitable - like their souls
are warmer.
To be an Objectivist (not my claim BTW) is to be able to study out an argument and reasonably describe it rather than jump to conclusions based on emotional attachment to ideology.
I've heard objectivists say that Rand bridged the is-ought gap because a human can have no value without life, therefore the highest value has to be the individuals life, with anything that benefits that life being morally valuable. Humans ought to value their lives above all else because without their livesnothing has value.
This is still taking into account the man who would die to save his dog or his country. He values his life primarily, but his life would lose most if not all of its value without freedom or his dog. He doesn't sacrifice himself, he trades his life for the things that are most valuable to the type of life he wants.
Absolute implies that it is not subject to the whims of any one person - that it is exterior to the subject. Morality may either be absolute (principles that apply to anyone and everyone) or it may be personal. This is one of the age-old fundamental questions of philosophy: the belief in the presence (or absence) of an absolute or universal moral code.
I perceive the situation thus: A) the posited existence of an absolute morality independent of any individual, B) the individual's perception/understanding of such a morality and C) the choice whether or not to adhere to it - all steps on a ladder. Alternately thus: existence, comprehension of existence, knowledge of scope and detail, and then choice to obey or disregard.
If one rejects the notion of universal morality, one immediately has decided that only moral relativism applies. The problem in this is that one is explicitly acknowledging factors that totally undermine society. Humanity depends on community/society for existence, so based on the evidence of society itself, I reject the idea of the absence of universal morality.
If one acknowledges the concept of universal morality, then comes the challenge of attempting to define it. Here is where the realm of a "personal" morality (as most people think of it) comes into play, but in reality it is not a change to the morality, but rather one's subjective interpretation of such. We do not actually have the power to define that morality (the laws of choice and consequence are outside our realm of control at the time being) and it exists independent of any given individual. All we can do is attempt to ascertain to the best of our knowledge, experience and learning what is entailed in this absolute morality. That is why there are hundreds of theologies and moral philosophies present in humanity - there is a lack of agreement on (and especially adherence to) what would comprise that single absolute morality (assuming of course that it exists).
In the case of the man and his dog, the man - under his personal interpretation of morality - determined that the risk of saving the dog (even at the cost of his own life) was a worthy transaction. That was a personal choice. Does it violate any kind of universal morality? I don't have any idea, and unless the man somehow reports to us on the consequences of his decision, I don't know that we can know with any certainty!
As for the others, yes, I agree. There is a post for abortion - I thought that one was enough for the time being, but have alluded to a couple of the others on various posts.
For Christians, one can look at things a couple of different ways. In a capital offense, the person has already been convicted of murder - the intentional taking of another's life. Many just want to send that person on to God for judgement with the perhaps uncharitable view that that individual has lost their chance to repent.
I don't believe in anything quite so cynical. I believe that we are protecting society and setting forth the penalty for murder and that this is the primary reason: to deter others from considering such a course of action.
The other point to contemplate is that those who are given the death sentence are not really any different from those given a prison sentence of a life term. In neither case is rehabilitation judged to be a probability. For all the cry and hue about "cruel and unusual punishment", why not languishing away in prison?
For atheists and liberals, I always get a lot of dancing around the subject and non-answers, so I can only speculate that the real reason they disagree is that they fear the unknown and they transfer this fear onto themselves as a proxy for the convict. That fear prevents them from condemning someone to cease to exist.
The thing that would be ironic if it weren't so tragic is that these same people in general support the principle of abortion, which is no less the termination of life than capital punishment and upon a person who is far less worthy of the punishment. I can find no rationale for this contradiction unless it is not a rationale, but rather fear which in fact is making the decision.
I also like the way you think of the death penalty, as a deterrent. Obviously it isn't going to stop all murders, I doubt anything really will, but it keeps rational people from committing murder. Or I should say borderline rational, as a mostly rational person very seldom contemplates going through with murder.
I don't think the death penalty really deters too many people though. I don't have a problem with death, I rarely talk about capital punishment cause it isn't very interesting to me. But I do like cost efficency, and while I'm not sure how much it costs to hand out a death sentence, I would say in most cases it would be more productive to reach an agreement with the murderer. I know it sounds ludicrous, but unless the person is full on insane I think you could find a use for him.
I'm not sure, maybe I'll think about it more and try to solidify my line of thought.
As for cost efficiency, you'll go south in a hurry if you go there because the current legal system is an endless maze of appeals and definitions of what constitutes "cruel and unusual punishment". Because of this legal morass, it is far more economical to pay $30,000+ a year (see http://www.vera.org/sites/default/files/...) for the life of the convict than the multiple millions it takes to exhaust the appeals process and eventually carry out the sentence. To me, this isn't as much a remark on the efficacy of capital punishment as it is on the non-efficacy of the criminal justice system itself, as well as a general commentary on society as a whole. :S
I too can only speculate about the atheists. But again, I don't see why they would have any qualms about capital punishment.
Really? That's a new one to me. A sin for the convict or the executioner? And what is the biblical justification for such a claim? That a curious stand.
Romans 13: "...rulers are not a cause of fear for good behavior, but for evil. Do you want to have no fear of authority? Do what is good and you will have praise from the same; for it is a minister of God to you for good. But if you do what is evil, be afraid; for it does not bear the sword for nothing; for it is a minister of God, an avenger who brings wrath on the one who practices evil."
That right there is the Christian justification FOR capital punishment.
The Bible is often mentioned in debates about the death penalty. Supporters quote the Exodus passage, eye for eye, while opponents appeal to Ezekiel (33:11): "As I live, says the Lord God, I swear I take no pleasure in the death of the wicked man, but rather in the wicked man's conversion, that he may live." In fact, such use of the Bible (finding a "proof text" to affirm one's point of view) is inappropriate.
Scripture scholars teach us to understand the Bible (and its individual books) in historical context: when it was written and why. Thus considered, there is an ambivalence about capital punishment in the Scriptures.
Clearly, the Hebrew Scriptures allowed the death penalty (for a much longer list of offenses than our society would be comfortable with—for example, striking or cursing a parent, adultery, idolatry). Yet, as we see in Ezekiel and many other passages, there is also an attempt to limit violence and to stress mercy. In the Christian Scriptures, Jesus' life and teachings (see the Sermon on the Mount, Matthew 5:1-7:29) focus on mercy, reconciliation and redemption. (It may also be instructive to recall that Jesus' death was itself an application of the death penalty.) The basic thrust of the Gospels supports opposition to the death penalty.
Indeed, the early Church (for example, in the writings of Clement of Rome [died 101 A.D.] and Justin Martyr [d. 165]) generally found taking human life to be incompatible with the gospel. Christians were not to participate in capital punishment. Later, after Christianity became the religion of the Roman Empire, opposition to the death penalty declined. Augustine recognized the death penalty as a means of deterring the wicked and protecting the innocent. In the Middle Ages, Thomas Aquinas reaffirmed this position.
The new Catechism of the Catholic Church reflects this tradition, stating that the death penalty is possible in cases of extreme gravity. However, the Catechism adds: "If bloodless means [that is, other than killing] are sufficient to defend human lives against an aggressor and to protect public order and the safety of persons, public authority should limit itself to such means, because they better correspond to the concrete conditions of the common good and are more in conformity to the dignity of the human person" (#2267). Clearly, then, the bishops' opposition to the death penalty is in accord with universal Church teaching.
The quote from Genesis predates even the OT Law of Moses, as it was given in the time of Noah. The Bible is clear and consistent on the capital punishment issue before the OT Law, during the OT Law, and after the OT Law.
The Apostle Paul even is seen saying in Acts 25 "I am standing before Caesar’s tribunal, where I ought to be tried. I have done no wrong to the Jews, as you also very well know. If, then, I am a wrongdoer and have committed anything worthy of death, I do not refuse to die; but if none of those things is true of which these men accuse me, no one can hand me over to them. I appeal to Caesar."
So, you can infer from his statement that though he did not believe he did anything worthy of death, he agreed in principle that there were actions that DID merit this punishment.
I applaud you for standing up for your beliefs - please don't misinterpret me. I just don't happen to agree with either the logical assertions being made nor do I accept the authority of the Catholic Church (and apparently neither does Lionel). What we have agreed on is the authority of the Bible, but not the interpretation thereof. Thus an impasse.
The Catholic bishops of the United States have provided careful guidance about this difficult issue, applying the teaching of the universal Church to our American culture. Along with the leadership assemblies of many Churches (for example. American Baptists, Disciples of Christ, Episcopalians, Lutherans, Presbyterians), the U.S. bishops have expressed their opposition to the death penalty. First articulated in 1974, the bishops' position is explained in a 1980 statement, Capital Punishment. Individual bishops and state conferences of bishops have repeated in numerous teachings their opposition to the death penalty.
In their 1980 statement, the bishops begin by noting that punishment, "since it involves the deliberate infliction of evil on another," must be justifiable. They acknowledge that the Christian tradition has for a long time recognized a government's right to protect its citizens by using the death penalty in some serious situations. The bishops ask, however, if capital punishment is still justifiable in the present circumstances in the United States.
In this context, the bishops enter the debate about deterrence and retribution. They acknowledge that capital punishment certainly prevents the criminal from committing more crimes, yet question whether it prevents others from doing so. Similarly, concerning retribution, the bishops support the arguments against death as an appropriate form of punishment. The bishops add that reform is a third reason given to justify punishment, but it clearly does not apply in the case of capital punishment. And so they affirm: "We believe that in the conditions of contemporary American society, the legitimate purposes of punishment do not justify the imposition of the death penalty."
As with the debate in our wider society, it is important to move behind the discussion of deterrence and retribution to get to the heart of the bishops' position. The statement does just that, by discussing four related values that would be promoted by the abolition of the death penalty.
First, "abolition sends a message that we can break the cycle of violence, that we need not take life for life, that we can envisage more humane and more hopeful and effective responses to the growth of violent crime." The bishops recognize that crime is rooted in the complex reality of contemporary society, including those "social conditions of poverty and injustice which often provide the breeding grounds for serious crime." More attention should go to correcting the root causes of crime than to enlarging death row.
Second, "abolition of capital punishment is also a manifestation of our belief in the unique worth and dignity of each person from the moment of conception, a creature made in the image and likeness of God." This belief, rooted in Scripture and consistently expressed in the social teach- ings of the Church, applies to all people, including those who have taken life.
Third, "abolition of the death penalty is further testimony to our conviction, a conviction which we share with the Judaic and Islamic traditions, that God is indeed the Lord of life." And so human life in all its stages is sacred, and human beings are called to care for life, that is, to exercise good stewardship and not absolute control. The bishops recognize that abortion, euthanasia and the death penalty are not the same issue, but they each point to the same fundamental value: safeguarding the sanctity of life.
Fourth, "we believe that abolition of the death penalty is most consonant with the example of Jesus." In many ways this final point summarizes the other three: the God revealed in the life of Jesus is a God of forgiveness and redemption, of love and compassion—in a word, a God of life. The heart of the bishops' position on the death penalty, then, is found in the gospel.
Gut-level reactions may cry out for vengeance, but Jesus' example in the Gospels invites all to develop a new and different attitude toward violence. The bishops encourage us to embody Jesus' message in practical and civic decisions.
You are welcome and have the right to hold to that philosophy. I can not reconcile the advocated position with either logic or theology and thereby politely decline.
You might be surprised, but I don't find these positions to be contradictory at all. You are also the rare one I have spoken to that holds both positions. Probably because people in the Gulch tend to be more pragmatic and logical rather than solely ideological. Kudos to you.
As I pointed out, the moral contradictions occur when one can not point out the need or moral justification for allowing someone deemed by society to be forever an enemy to such to continue to live off society. I can respect any position as well as it is reasonable - it is the irreconcilable contradictions that rub me wrong.
That said, I also don't take everything espoused by the Catholic church hierarchy as "gospel." As you say, they are men, and men are fallible (and no, I don't believe in the infallibility of the Pope).
The "purist" O's will say that I cannot do that, that I must accept all teaching of those in the hierarchy of my faith otherwise I don't really hold with my faith. That's bogus, as I can come to my own conclusions as well as the church hierarchy.
The first question that has to be answered, as a precondition of any attempt to define, to judge or to accept any specific system of ethics, is: Why does man need a code of values?
Let me stress this. The first question is not: What particular code of values should man accept? The first question is: Does man need values at all—and why?" AR, The Virtue of Selfishness
The code of values derives from Man qua Man
One can not act without values. Self-determination presupposes the ability to evaluate one's current position in comparison to a future position. If one has no values, one has no basis for comparison and therefore can not act. The need for values is therefore presupposed and inherent when one defines man as being self-aware. There is no great moral mystery here. The question is really about which morality (value system) to adopt.
For example, computer code is just exactly that: a value system. Without it, the computer sits lifeless and useless. With it, it now has instructions on which it can perform computations and work.
No, the first question is this: "Presupposing that man has the capability to act, the key lies in defining HOW he should act, i.e. which set of rules should govern his decisions."
Now, since we have put that away, how about the genesis of this whole thread - are those codes absolute? A computer program is absolute. That code can provide for different choice given inputs (the "if, then, else" situation), but you cannot violate the fundamentals of what the code means - "if" checks one thing against something else. You can either find that it agrees or doesn't agree, but you cannot come to the conclusion "blue."
Ironic that you posted the example of computer code, as I agree with you and used exactly the same analogy elsewhere on this very thread!
Great minds must think alike. Or something :)
Religion is simply one's way of life.
: the belief in a god or in a group of gods
: an organized system of beliefs, ceremonies, and rules used to worship a god or a group of gods
: an interest, a belief, or an activity that is very important to a person or group
If you only use the 3rd definition, I can see how you might come to that position. That is not the common definition.
Given that, do you believe that what one holds as important is the only thing that defines the moral code? Are there not things outside of the specific individual's sphere of importance that have an impact on morality?
Until we can define and control the consequences for actions, it is pure illusion to believe that humans have any ability to control what I will call natural morality. We can pass laws to whatever effect we want. It really doesn't matter how well intentioned (or not) we are, we have no power to rebut these natural laws and their consequences.
I will use the example of sexual promiscuity. One of the results of unfettered sexual activity is the probability that one will contract one of the many sexually transmitted diseases. Despite society's permissiveness regarding sexual norms, traditional values most accurately reflected this reality: if you have sex with multiple partners, you take a high medical risk. On the other hand, if you remain chaste and monogamous, your probability of contracting one of these diseases drops to zero!
The natural laws of economics are the same way. No matter how much governmental officials want to believe in Keynesian economic theory, it runs contrary to natural economics and therefore always fails as a consequence. Taking money from the private sector so government can spend it has never and can not provide efficient or lasting private sector growth. High tax policies result in a retarded private sector economy. Those are laws of nature that can not be re-written - no matter how hard progressives want to believe otherwise.
"Do no harm." This simple statement implies that I can differentiate one person from another and that I have self-awareness: I can differentiate myself and my limits from my environment and I can recognize the presence and boundaries of other self-aware entities. On top of that, I accept that just as I value my own self-awareness and self-determination, others may come to the same conclusion. My own actions and boundaries are delimited when they have an effect on others.
The problem with the statement "do no harm" is that it is also highly nebulous and subject to several nullifying conditions. "Harm" indicates damage or an adverse effect, which I may or may not be able to properly perceive with respect to the other person. Unless that other person shares my same level of knowledge and morality, what I may interpret as "harm" may not equate to theirs. Further, what if in order to remove an injured victim from a burning building I must move them and risk exacerbating the existing injury? I will do harm either way. Therefore I find this statement to be too dependent on subjective rationalization to be useful as a moral code.
The second realization is that we are not individual creatures: we can not survive on our own. Humankind requires society for economics, procreation, etc. So in our personal search for a moral code, we must also search for a moral code that best fits not only for ourselves, but also fits others. Thus is derived the push for evangelicalism - the attempt to harmonize the moral codes of society on a single base. Out of this grows society itself.
Since we have derived that man must individually choose morality, but that society must agree on a joint morality in order to function, it is reasonable for our cooperative moral code to than apply to everyone the same way - or to be absolute. Those who violate society's moral codes are then cast out or confined. So I would argue that morality is absolute first in the social context of the social contract.
Second, we must also evaluate that if each individual is seeking their own betterment, but that we are bound together as a society, then the aggregate result is that society - as a function of individual self-determination - is also seeking for betterment. In this way, we are also seeking for a unifying set of principles that enables all the full rights of self-expression while lifting society as a whole. This sought-for societal morality will also be absolute - even if it is conceptual.
So yes, morality is absolute - from either an individual or a societal standpoint - but we individually have the self-determination to either adopt and practice that absolute morality or not.
Morality meets the test of an absolute. The Law of Identity
Ethics and Morality are blood brothers just like geometry and algebra can be expressed in similar ways
http://westernrifleshooters.wordpress.co...
"Very well, as individuals we all die. This brings us to the second half of the question: Does homo sapiens AS A BREED have to die? The answer is: No, it is NOT unavoidable.
We have two situations, mutually exclusive: Mankind surviving, and mankind extinct. With respect to morality, the second situation is a null class. An extinct breed has NO behavior, moral or otherwise.
Since survival is the sine qua non, I now define “moral behavior” as “behavior that tends toward survival.” I won’t argue with philosophers or theologians who choose to use the word “moral” to mean something else, but I do not think anyone can define “behavior that tends toward extinction” as being “moral” without stretching the word “moral” all out of shape.
We are now ready to observe the hierarchy of moral behavior from its lowest level to its highest."
Read the whole speech. It's worth reading... I personally really like the part about the baboons. And at the end of the speech maybe you'll meet Jeff Allen... and me.
"The simplest form of moral behavior occurs when a man or other animal fights for his own survival. Do not belittle such behavior as being merely selfish. Of course it is selfish. . .but selfishness is the bedrock on which all moral behavior starts and it can be immoral only when it conflicts with a higher moral imperative. An animal so poor in spirit that he won’t even fight on his own behalf is already an evolutionary dead end; the best he can do for his breed is to crawl off and die, and not pass on his defective genes."